Interview Transcript-Peter
Godfrey-Smith
FRANCESCA: If we squeeze the entire history of the Earth into one single year,
humans would show up in the last 30 minutes of the final hour. But life has
been around for way longer, about 3.7 billion years. So what has all that life
been up to all this time?
In his latest book, Living on Earth, philosopher Peter Godfrey Smith offers a
fresh look at how living things have shaped our planet. His previous books,
Other Minds and Metazoa, dove into the mystery of how conscious minds emerged
on Earth.
But in Living on Earth, he flips the script and explores what happens when we
see organisms as active creators, not just products of evolution. The planet we
live on is largely the result of the work of other living beings, who shape the
environments that we now are so drastically modifying.
And what lesson does that hold for our relationship to the other creatures with
whom we share this wondrous and beautiful planet? Maybe kinship is the answer.
It's the frame Peter Godfrey Smith suggests and applies to such issues as the
lives of domestic animals and how we should approach wilderness.
Peter Godfrey Smith is a professor in the School of History and Philosophy of
Science at the University of Sydney, where he researches the philosophies of
biology and the mind. Living on Earth is his seventh book.
Peter Godfrey Smith, welcome to Writer's Voice.
PGS: It's a pleasure to be here.
FR: This book, Living on Earth, is fundamentally, I think, about the nature of
our relationship to the world around us and the life that inhabits the world
with us. What compelled you to write this book, understanding that in some ways
it's the third in a series, but this one in particular?
PGS: Yes, the fact that it's the third in a series was important. The first one
was built around a particular part of the history of animal life, this deep
fork in the evolutionary tree that on one road leads to us, on the other road
leads to octopuses and various other animals.
The second one was about many more animals, most animal groups, but all the way
through those books the emphasis was on the idea of the mind as a product, as
something that evolution had built, had installed on the scene, and there is
the other side, which is the mind as cause rather than the mind as effect, and
it was always sitting there as the other element or the other aspect that had
to be told.
The geneticist Richard Lewontin, a scientist who died a few years ago after a
very distinguished career at Harvard, he always made a big thing about the idea
that when describing evolutionary processes you shouldn't just describe living
things as outcomes, as products, as effects.
The world that we are dealing with is in many ways, in large part, shaped by
what they've done, and in the case of some organisms, certainly us, as a
consequence of what we've decided to do. So the mind-as-cause angle was missing
from the story and had to be put back in.
FR: So in other words, not only must we understand the effect of the world on
us, but our effect on the world.
PGS: That's right. In another conversation I had about the book, a phrase came
up, which I've come to think of as a very useful way of thinking about the
book, which is that much of the book is a kind of a history of choice, an
evolutionary history of choice.
And part of the point of the book is that we walk through the evolutionary
history of choice, of efficacy, of organisms doing things, and then in the last
part of the book, the third chunk of chapters, it's time to start thinking about
how we might improve our choices in the light of our understanding of that
history.
So although I don't think there's a kind of direct line, you know, here's how
the past was, here's what we should do now, I don't think it's like that.
The hope is that there's such a thing as a kind of informing of our reflections
on our next steps that can come out of the history of choice.
FR: Right. And when you talk about choice, I mean, we're jumping ahead a bit,
so I think we'll probably go back to it in more depth, but that also implies
that there is a right of choice of other beings on this planet, not just us.
PGS: A right of choice. That's interesting. I don't think it implies that. I
see the sequence of ideas.
And I hadn't thought of it, I hadn't thought about it from that angle before.
Let me just have a second to think about that, because this really is a
different way of phrasing it.
FR: And maybe just to clarify it, I'm really thinking of right in terms of a
moral choice, in the way that you talk about morality, about ethics later on in
the book.
FR: That's how I interpreted the question, and that's what was a bit
unexpected. Let me just think about that for a second.
I guess I don't think that, and I don't think it's implied. So how did you put
it? I mean, I realize this threatens to mess things up. It's just too
interesting not to do it properly, though.
FR: Yeah, because when you said that we have made choices, that it's a question
of choice, not just that we change the world because we're not thinking about
it, but it's just happening. It's not a byproduct.
We're changing the world through intention. But I think that your book really
does imply, I mean, that's not just a human thing. I mean, other animals also
do that.
And it felt to me that in the latter part of your book, in the last two
chapters, you were really arguing that not only do animals do that, but that
they have a right to have that ability preserved.
I mean, thinking particularly in terms of your critique of industrialized
farming, factory farming.
PGS: I don't think it's implied. I don't think it's something that's a kind of
an automatic or even for me an entirely natural consequence of those earlier
chapters. What we reach is an understanding of the role that choice has played.
We reflect on our own capacity to choose.
And one of the things that we have to work out is how to value various things
that can happen in the lives of other animals, including their choices,
including the suffering and the well-being that they undergo, and so on.
The idea of rights as in some sense naturally given or as following from very
general observations about the world is one that I do resist, and that's just
part of my ethical orientation in philosophy.
I think that rights are political constructs, basically. They're very good
political constructs, you know, I value them as political constructs, but I
don't think of rights as things that are inherent in nature pretty much at all.
And that is a somewhat controversial thing to say.
Now given that, when we look around at other animals, non-human animals, and
think both about the kinds of lives they live in the wild and the kinds of
lives that we've imposed upon them, one thing that we need to do, I think, is
to change the way that we value various of their activities and our
actions.
Bestowing rights is one kind of somewhat politically guided way of approaching
that.
Another way of handling it is merely to try to reduce suffering. And I think
that's entirely coherent.
It doesn't really go through the pathway of consideration of rights. You can
express it in terms of a right not to suffer needlessly, or something like
that.
But in philosophy, the utilitarian tradition has tended to just directly argue
from the badness of suffering to a kind of responsibility we have to reduce it.
And that's a viable path too.
Your question is very interesting. I hadn't thought about it in the particular
way that you have phrased it. I hadn't thought about it at all like that.
The idea that reflection on the history of choice as part of the history of the
Earth might motivate us to recognize a right to choose as a general feature of
things. It's attractive. I find myself resisting it a little, in part because
of this general commitment to not seeing rights as naturally given, but as
political constructs. And then thinking that I'm not sure that the best way
forward to improve our relationships with non-human nature is through this
concept, is through the concept of a right.
As you can tell, this really has me thinking. I may get off this call and
decide and rethink some of these things. It's a very thought-provoking
angle.
FR: Well, I'm honored to be able to provoke you in that way. So what you're
saying, in a way, there's two ways.
One is rights as a kind of legalistic framework, which in some sense is
probably necessary for us to reduce the suffering of animals.
So if we want to include an understanding of how human beings are going to
choose to do something, some sense of legal rights is important, and legal
rights are rooted in our cultural understanding of them, and hence our cultural
understanding then can be informed by the compassion that we feel.
Because I think the other way of looking at it, when you say to reduce
suffering, is to develop our compassion, our understanding of compassion.
And I don't think that the two are opposed to each other, they may just be
different parts of the same process of us arriving at the point where we can in
fact effectively honor the other lives and reduce their suffering.
Let me say a couple of things in response to that, and my comments pick up
different parts of it.
The idea of rights as inherently political I think of as a little different
from the idea that they always have to be installed in law, in a legalistic
framework.
One way of looking at the animal rights movement over recent decades is to say
that we want to do better in this area, and a concept that has been treated, I
think, in valuable ways as a creature to improve human life and human
societies, the idea of a right, can be exported into this other domain and we
can just say that, look, animals have a right not to be treated as badly as
they have been. Even if it's not legalistically understood, it's a way of
exporting a useful concept that has a home in human political, social, legal
life.
And I think that's often fine, and now I'll jump ahead to a different idea. In
the second last chapter, one of the things I grapple with and found quite hard
to think about is our proper response to suffering in wild nature, in wild
systems, the suffering that results from the ordinary actions of predators,
just the sorts of things that happen to wild animals.
And some philosophers have argued for, or taken seriously, the idea that we
should if we can. I mean, very hard to do it in practical ways, but ideally we
might try to intervene and reduce suffering in wild nature. Jeff McMahon,
Martha Nussbaum in different ways have taken this idea seriously, for example.
And I don't go down that road.
Now I don't go down that road because I reflect on the rights that they do and
don't have. You know, do animals have the right not to suffer? If they do, do
they have the right not to suffer at the hands of other animals? Do the other
animals have a right to pursue their predatory instincts and so on?
Using the notion of right in that discussion is one way of proceeding, trying
to sort through and work out where the rights are, who has them and who
doesn't.
And I didn't go down that road, partly again because I think of rights as tools
for dealing with problems in political and social and ethical life. And this
problem, I think, is probably better handled with different concepts.
Now I'm not sure what those better concepts are. The way I put it in the book
at one point is that we should take seriously the kinship we have with
non-human wild animals and also feel a kind of gratitude to the evolutionary
process that gave rise to us. And that should affect how we treat those
animals.
Now that reflection, somewhat vague and difficult as it was, it's not really a
rights-based train of thought at all. It's a different kind of thing.
Yeah, so that I think gives me a better response to your question, the idea
that in some settings when we're dealing with these problems, bringing in the
concept of a right I think is useful. In other contexts I think it's perhaps
not the most useful way to approach them.
FR: And also, you know, really when you talk about kinship, I think, I mean I
can't but help but put that within the context of how human beings actually did
think about our relationship with the rest of the world for, you know, hundreds
of thousands of years of evolution and it's still the way that many indigenous
cultures think of.
You know, here the tribes, Native tribes in the American continent, talk about
"all our relations" when they're speaking of the rest of the living
beings on Earth.
So that it actually goes back to our ancient way of thinking about this and one
that, you know, did not bring us to the brink of extinction like the current
one is doing.
PGS: Yes, I do endorse that line of thought. I didn't make much of it in this
book.
One thing I was very wary of, very conscious of, is I don't think that people
should cherry pick aspects of Indigenous belief systems and just bring them
into a discussion that has quite a different character and say, well, you know,
look, here's a point of commonality with this particular Indigenous belief
system.
And here in Australia, the Australian context is full of ideas that are
suggestive on this front and the idea of kinship is definitely one of them. But
it really does come as a package, it comes as a big package of ideas, and the
cherry picking instinct is one that I wanted to resist. So while I resonate to
the idea, I didn't make it part of the argument of the book.
FR: So let's go back to the beginning. Let's go back to the whole notion of
looking at life from the point of view of life as cause. And you actually start
really with the beginning.
You start with cyanobacteria. I mean, we don't have the time to go through all
the wonderful natural history that is in this book, Living on Earth, Peter
Godfrey Smith. But this was such a striking one. Cyanobacteria, probably as far
back as we can go in the chain of life, completely changing our planet.
PGS: Right. It's a wonderful part of the story, the fact that not only has the
transformation of the planet by organisms been such a long-standing process
that goes back so far, but also perhaps one of the handful of most massive
transforming agents was this early case, these early episodes involving
cyanobacteria.
They began filling the atmosphere with oxygen gas, which made possible animal
life.
But also, and this is something that was one of the pleasures of writing this
book and one of the challenges, was learning some earth science and realizing
just the magnitude of these causal factors.
It's not just that oxygen in the atmosphere changes the viability of animals,
makes it possible to live like us with nerves and muscles and brains, it
changes the whole geology of the planet. You get different kinds of minerals
appearing, you get different kinds of cycles with respect to all the other
elements that are moving through the system.
But the earth becomes a different place as a consequence of the filling of the
atmosphere with this highly reactive, almost aggressively reactive gas. And
that was the first big transformation. So as you say, part of the book is about
that first massive series of transforming events.
And then a series of episodes that I also enjoyed learning more about were the
effects of land plants, the effects of land plants on rivers, which in turn
affect mountains, the whole shape of the land being affected by the actions of
plants with their root systems, with the way that they shape the land.
FR: I'm glad that you brought in plants there because this book, while in many
ways focuses more on animals, most of it does, plants are also involved. And I
had to think of, I remember when I was talking with Amitav Ghosh about his book
about the history of the opium trade, Smoke and Ashes, and he said that he
thought that opium actually created the opium trade, much in the way that you
talk about how life is a cause. He came to look upon it as some conscious being
that actually created the need for this opium trade that, of course, had
incredible effects on human history.
PGS: Yes, Michael Pollan, if I remember rightly, has written in similar ways
about food plants, the idea that wheat, for example, is a kind of an agent and
its choices, or quasi-choices, its strategies are affecting how we behave to
its benefit and so on. I didn't pursue that line of thought in the book. I've
always been a little bit skeptical about it without knowing completely
why.
There is a sense in which various of these plants have done things that, in a
way mediated by our choices and decisions, have led to them becoming vastly
more widespread, achieving a kind of ecological dominance. And then the
question is whether you should describe that in strongly strategic or
choice-based terms, and with a certain amount of caution I came to think of
that as going too far. If part of the point of the book is to give a history of
choice, you want to be careful not to see choice in places where it's not
really present or only metaphorically present. And the idea of plants
manipulating us in those ways, again with some caution, I think is going too
far.
FR: Yeah, that makes some sense to me. And also it makes some sense when you
come to talking about the Gaia Theory. I mean this is a theory which has
entranced me for decades. I want it to be true. I feel in some sense that it is
true, but that's a feeling. So where that feeling comes from, it's certainly
not based on evidence. So there are uses to that construct, but there also are
limitations. Talk a little bit about that. And we're talking about the Gaia
hypothesis of Lovelock, right?
PGS: Yeah, James Lovelock and Lynn Margulis also. Yeah, well in a way I come
from it in the opposite, in a way that's the opposite of the way you approach
it. I have always instinctively thought, no, this is going too far. I don't
believe this. It's a bit fluffy.
It's extending certain concepts, the idea of an organism into places where
those concepts don't belong. The whole earth contains a lot of organisms, but
to say that it is an organism in its own right, I've always thought is
excessive.
And then I began reading some of the more recent and careful and critical
discussions of this idea, especially in the work of Tim Lenton, who I talk
about in a bit of detail in the book. Also, Ford Doolittle, a biologist who has
a book on this topic, a whole book on Gaia coming out later this year, and they
press against my skepticism a little bit, especially Lenton. I mean, the
argument of Tim Lenton is, yeah, perhaps Lovelock was going too far, Lovelock
and Margulis were going too far when they said that you can think of the whole
Earth as an organism.
But if you drop that idea completely, you still have to deal with the fact that
there are lots of cycles and processes on the Earth that look surprisingly
friendly to the continuation of living activity. All sorts of things you'd
think could go in different directions tend to go in a direction that keeps
factors like the temperature, the amount of oxygen in the atmosphere, the
amount of salt in the sea, which is a case I found interesting, all of those
variables are kept within somewhat friendly ranges for life.
And Lenton's argument is, okay, right, perhaps the Earth is not an organism,
that was going too far, but now give me a story about why all these cycles
should be behaving in a fairly consistently life-friendly way. And that
challenge I found quite hard to deal with in the book, and I think some of it
is just luck, some of it just has to be regarded as luck.
And that's true even on his view. For example, before life gets going there has
to be a decent amount of water on a planet. And Lenton says that a lot of the
water was brought in on asteroids. That's why the Earth had a good amount of
water early on. Now that's not something that can have a Gaia-like explanation.
That has to be luck. The fact that water will be useful in the formation of
life at a later stage can't call it into Earth, even on the most ambitious
Gaia-like view.
And once we get used to some of these things being just a matter of luck, you
can see perhaps we should just get used to that more generally. Lenton doesn't
buy it, and I thank him a lot in the acknowledgments of the book, and engaging
with him on this topic was always a very productive and challenging part of the
process.
So I've always been a skeptic about Gaia, I've always thought it was going too
far, and some people have pushed me in ways that give me pause, as they
say.
FR: And so consciousness, first of all, I'd like to ask you to define it. What
is consciousness? How widespread do you think it is in the world?
PGS: The word consciousness has acquired a broader meaning in these discussions
than it used to have. And I used to resist this broadening, but I've given up
resisting. It basically now refers to just the presence of feelings of any
kind, of the fact that an organism or any other system, there's something it
feels like to be that system.
So in these recent discussions, to say that a squid is conscious is just to say
that it feels like something to be a squid. And as I say, I used to resist this
way of talking, but it's just the way the discussion has gone.
So let's say the question is, which systems in the world are such that it feels
like something to be those systems or those organisms? And I don't think it
feels like something to be the whole earth. I think that even if you think that
Gaia is, the earth is an organism, it's a further step to think of it as a
conscious organism.
I don't think plants are conscious also, but I think it's very common,
probably, in animal life. I think the list of conscious animals extends beyond
our relatives, other primates, other mammals, extends beyond fish and birds
into at least some invertebrates.
The cases that there's now a pretty good case for, a pretty good argument for,
are octopuses and to some extent other cephalopods, crustaceans like lobsters
and crabs, and insects in some ways. They used to be the real borderline cases,
where there was not particularly good evidence, and now the general trend has
been toward it being, I think, fairly likely that there's something it feels
like, even to be an insect.
FR: Yeah, and there's been some recent work that implies that plants also have
that kind of consciousness, that when you cut them, they recoil, they certainly
create defensive substances. So it really just may be a fact of the limitation
of our own scientific knowledge to acknowledge consciousness among
plants.
PGS: I don't buy it, but I'm not sure. In the plant case, one of the things
that's argued a little bit in this book, but also in the previous book, is that
nervous systems are special.
Nervous systems, I think, really make a huge difference in this area, and
plants don't have them. They have signaling systems, as you say. They have all
sorts of ways of coordinating defenses, but you could have a system that had
signaling systems and ways of coordinating defenses that was not conscious, I
think.
I mean, various robots are also, I think, places to think about here. Now,
plants are alive, unlike the robots, and there can be an argument that living
activity itself makes a big difference here. I resist that to some extent. I
think nervous systems are where the action is with respect to experience.
FR: So I usually don't do this, but I am jumping around because when you talk,
it just brings up other points in the book, and this was one I particularly was
interested in. Well, I was interested in just about everything, but this one
really struck me, which is that you think that there are real limitations to
artificial intelligence, to robots, that there are certain things robots can't
and will never be able to do. Talk about that and why.
PGS: I think that systems that are made in the way that present-day computers
are made and the controllers in robots, to the extent that they use ordinary
computer hardware as the controllers, it's not that I think they can't be very
complicated and smart and have a kind of intelligence, but I think experience
or consciousness, sentience, I think there's probably a real gap there.
And this follows again from the special features of nervous systems. If you
look at a brain or another nervous system, the way we're used to thinking about
it in a lot of these discussions is that, well, it's a big network. You've got
things that switch on and off, other things, this neuron fires, it makes that
neuron fire.
It's a big network and networks can exist in computers as well. And you could
have a very similar structure inside a computer to what is in a person's
brain.
Now, I think that line of thinking ignores some important features of nervous
systems and brains, as well as the sort of networky, somewhat computer-like
activities in brains.
There are what can be called the large-scale dynamic patterns, the rhythmic
oscillations that extend over the whole system, and are not reducible to just
those point-to-point influences. They're really a distinctive feature of brains
that has been underplayed.
Now, some neuroscientists for decades, including Francis Crick of DNA fame,
Wolfsinger, some other important neuroscientists, have long suspected that felt
experience or consciousness has a connection to those oscillatory large-scale
patterns that are distinctive to nervous systems, and I pretty much endorse that
idea. No one knows for sure, I could be wrong, everyone pronouncing on this
question could be wrong, but that's where I put my bets.
And present-day computer hardware is very different, it's just physically
different. It's a physically different sort of object from a brain.
Now we could perhaps one day design different computer hardware that was very
brain-like, that had the same kind of mixture of the network features and those
large-scale rhythmic oscillations with the two interacting. We might build something
like that.
I talk about this at one point in the book, I was talking at a conference a
year or so ago and I was talking about exactly what we're discussing now, and I
found myself saying, well, this is an invitation to people to design different
hardware, different sorts of objects, and have computers physically different
from how they are now.
And I woke up the next morning after this talk and I thought, well, is that
really such a good idea? If there's a sort of a barrier there between computers
as they are and consciousness or felt experience, maybe that's not a bad thing,
that barrier, and maybe it's not a barrier that we should be rushing to break
down.
Especially because if we start building simple, well, not simple, but simpler
than human systems that we have reason to believe are sentient or conscious,
we've then got to start worry about what their lives are like, and it's
reasonable to suspect that at certain stages the ones we build might not have a
good time at all. It might be quite a cruel practice that we find ourselves
engaged in.
So I ended up thinking that if there's a barrier between the I side of AI, the
intelligence side of AI, and consciousness, and that barrier is a matter of the
hardware, the physical machines, maybe that's not a bad thing, that
barrier.
FR: I couldn't agree more, and that actually brings us back to where we began
in this conversation, and that is to factory farming, how we treat other
animals. You say that you want to motivate and end to factory farming, and you
use the idea of a life worth living and something called the reincarnation
test.
Talk about that.
PGS: Yeah. I think that factory farming is pretty much the worst thing that
humans do, at least to non-humans. There's plenty of bad things we do to other
humans, but in the non-human realm, this is the biggest problem, and quite a
few moral theories, philosophical approaches have come to converge or agree on
this, but I'm not entirely happy with the way that existing discussions are set
up, so I approach it again from scratch and think that a life worth living,
that's a useful idea, and we should ask whether it's appropriate for us with
our powers to give large numbers of animals a life that's not worth living, a
life so bad that it would have been better not to have lived at all.
Now I don't think all farming is like that, but I think modern industrialised
farming, especially of pigs and chickens, those are perhaps the two really
conspicuous cases, I think it is like that. I think the lives are not worth
living.
I think that if you just read a sort of sketch of what those lives are
typically like, just a page-long sketch or something like that, and then you
ask yourself, after I die, would I rather come back and live a life like that,
or just have things end, not come back at all?
I think of that as a way of asking about the difference between a life worth
living and a life not worth living. And if you think you'd rather not come back
at all, that's a way of judging that these lives, these other animals' lives,
are not worth living. And I certainly wouldn't want to come back as an animal
living within an intensive modern factory farming context.
I wouldn't mind coming back as an animal on a really good humane farm. I think
that's a very different case.
I'm not really an anti-farming person, but I think that the drive for profit,
the fact that the numbers of animals have become so huge and control has become
so mechanized has led to an imposition on them of a really, in many cases, the
kinds of lives that we with our powers should not be imposing on
anything.
FR: Yes, and whether it's a right or not, really what you're arguing is that we
develop that compassion, that sense of compassion is about putting yourself in
somebody else's shoes and seeing how does that feel and feeling how they feel.
And I think that's so important.
You make another point too when it comes to farming that is what you call
humane farming.
And of course, we want to make sure that what's called humane is certified
humane.
But you make a point that I've often made to people who say that we shouldn't
eat animals at all, which is if we don't eat cows and pigs and chickens, many
of them will disappear from the earth because people are not going to be
raising herds and herds of cows as pets.
PGS: That's right. In a gentle way, I do want to criticize some of the
campaigns that are mounted on this front where people say, you know, this is
the life these animals should have. They should be carefree lives in the
fields.
Now, if we move to a completely plant-based diet, a completely plant-based food
system, it's not that there'll be large numbers of cows and pigs living
carefree lives in the fields. It'll be the end of that kind of existence, that
kind of animal life.
And you might think that's fine, and I know plenty of people who think, yes,
right, it would be better if the kind of being that a domesticated cow or
chicken is just no longer existed because there's no way of making that into a
decent life.
I do think there are reasonable different responses here. And in the book, I
take time to map out some approaches different to mine that I have respect for,
and a kind of total abolitionism, just turning our back on farming and letting
non-human animal life just go its own way. It is an attitude that I have
respect for. I see the point of it.
I think that there's a first round of decision-making that we confront when
thinking about modern factory farming where the answers are fairly clear. We
should stop doing these things.
And then there are some harder questions. Do we want farm animals to exist at
all? Is there any regime under which we can feel it's justified? If we turn our
back on them, should we then worry about the fact that the remnants might have
quite difficult lives?
If we rewild the descendants of farm animals, should we worry about the fact
that they may suffer in wild nature in ways that were preventable by us if we'd
done things differently?
The general picture here is one in which I organize it around these two rounds of
decision-making. We first got to think about modern industrialized farming, and
I think change what we do.
First of all, I think there are lots of disagreements where I have a lot of
respect for different views, and the consideration you raise about a future
without, at all, various animals of these kinds, it's part of this second round
of questioning.
FR: Right, and then you also move to the question of wildlife and habitat. I
found it interesting, you say the two great environmental crises that we face
are climate chaos, climate change, climate disruption, and habitat loss for
wildlife, and that the latter has not been sufficiently examined or, you know,
sufficiently promoted.
Now, clearly climate is a threat to habitat, but if we stopped all fossil fuel
use tomorrow, we would still be destroying habitats because of the way our
society works, our economies work. So talk about habitat disruption and how
that fits into, you know, the larger goal of the book, which is to make us
understand what our place is in the world in relationship to all the other
living beings that we live on it with.
PGS: Right. In relation to those two crises that you mentioned, climate change
and habitat destruction, I do want to argue for a partial reweighting of our
priorities here.
It's not that I think that climate change isn't a big problem, but it has been
allowed to completely dominate discussion in a lot of areas in a way that has
nudged out or edged out concern over habitat destruction.
And people sometimes say, well, that's because, you know, if we don't do better
on climate, then the habitats will be wrecked. And one thing I want to do is
assert more of a separation between the two.
As you say, we could in principle do much better on climate, but continue to
pollute, continue to let forests get cut down, continue to see animals such as
birds and insects lose colossal numbers over a relatively short period of time.
There's that possibility.
We could also, in principle, put less effort into climate change and put enormous
effort into habitat preservation and restoration. We could try to construct or,
you know, create really large reserves through which the effects of climate
change could at least be blunted a bit because animals could move around, could
find different places and so on.
Now it's not that I think we should do the second. I think that climate change
should remain a priority. But I do think they're separable questions or
separable problems. Probably the features of a climate change discussion that I
most wanted to sort of press on in a somewhat unorthodox way, well, there are
two.
There are two aspects of contemporary discussion of the climate crisis that I
do want to push back on a little bit, and there are two ways in which my view
is a bit unorthodox. One is this separation between the problems.
I think we should take habitat destruction more seriously in its own right. I
mean, one thing it's worth reflecting on there is the fact that local action,
local decisions are very efficacious in the case of habitat preservation.
If one state, one country, one region decides to preserve what it has, that
need not be washed out by the failures of others elsewhere.
So one is the separation.
FR: And just to interject, that puts me in mind of the whole movement that I'm
part of and that is really growing, which is people developing pollinator
gardens on their own land and in their communities.
JBS: Right. Right. So it's a paradigm case of something which is extremely
local, but efficacious because pollination is so important.
The other thing that I want to push back on a little bit in this discussion is
the kind of doomsday language that's used, the way in which people now paint
really grim pictures of the future, global boiling and uninhabitable earth and
things like that.
And I push back a bit on that because I think it's not entirely accurate. If
you go back in the history of the earth to a time when, for example, the earth
was 5 degrees Celsius warmer than now, you don't reach some nightmare
hellscape.
You reach a place that's warmer, but it's a place where, for example, the great
apes were diverging from other primates. You reach a different stage in the
dynamic earth. It's not, I think, inherently worse.
The problem of our present situation is the speed of change, the fact that
adaptation is going to be so difficult given how fast things are changing. And
I don't want to downplay the size of that problem, but both the separation of
climate change from habitat preservation and, I think, the unwise way in which
doomsday language is used. Those are two things where I do want to push a
little against orthodoxy.
FR: Well, this has been just an amazing discussion, like your book. It's a book
that really I want to reread a number of times because it really brings a different
perspective, I think, when we are looking through the lens of how we act upon
the world. It puts us in a place that allows us to take on a much more
appropriate responsibility for it.
PGS: Well, this was a very challenging and enjoyable conversation, so thank you
for having me on.